Difference between revisions of "Course:Law3020/2014WT1/Group C/Liberty & Paternalism"
Line 51: | Line 51: | ||
=== Application of Liberty and Paternalism to Moore v. British Columbia (Education) === | === Application of Liberty and Paternalism to Moore v. British Columbia (Education) === | ||
− | The | + | The Court in Moore v. British Columbia (Education) uphold the presumption of individual liberty; specifically, the liberty of students to develop their individual potential and acquire the knowledge and skills needed to contribute to a healthy democratic society through education. This liberty is protected in the acknowledgement by the provincial government that there is an inherent right to access to education under section 8 of the British Columbia Human Rights Code. Further, the Code also set out the limits of which the government must adhere in order to prevent discrimination against individuals on the basis of this right and the liberty is protects. These facts strongly follow Mill’s concept of individual liberty and the idea that the creation of political rights and liberties is one way to ensure limits on authoritative powers from infringing liberty. |
− | + | It is important to note that the Court stresses the importance of how all children should be afforded equal opportunities to develop their full potential through education. In fact, the Court goes as far as to stress the importance of protection of children against the harm of receiving poor education or limited access to the education they need. In Jeffrey’s case, at the Tribunal level, experts clearly agreed that Jeffrey suffered as a result of having poor access to facilities to address his disability and noted sufficient access to those facilities would have benefitted him in the long run. The Court here submits that the public school system has a duty to provide sufficient access to education. These ideas fit Mills presumption that the doctrine of Liberty is only applicable to those of mature faculties and that those who do not have them, children under the legal age or ‘nonage’ societies’, must be protected by those that do against harm from their own actions (in this case, Jeffrey) and actions of others (in this case, the school district and Province). | |
− | + | This idea of protection of children against harm easily brings in the liberalism theory of the Harm Principle set out by Mill. The Harm Principle allows the restriction of individual liberty by law if it promotes the prevention of serious harm towards others in society. In Jeffrey’s case, the ‘others’ in society are those children with special educational needs, and the ‘harm’ that occurs is their inability to access education to allow full liberty to develop their skills and knowledge. In this case, the actions of the school district did not meet this justification. Their actions were stressed as being one of economic needs to allow the cutbacks to the programs for special needs students that Jeffrey required. Further, the actions by the school district indiscriminately allowed some programs, such as the Outdoor School, while cutting others, such as the Diagnostic Centre. At no point did the actions of the school district seek to prevent harm to special needs children in the education system, of which, had the school district sought to do so it may have allowed the limits they imposed under the Harm Principle. This is extremely prevalent in the decision by the school district to not even consider alternative options for special needs children in their public schools before cutting the programs completely. | |
+ | Paternalism notes that not only are limits against liberty justified in situations of harm to others as stressed by Mill, but Dworkin allows limits against liberty as justified in situations of harm to the individuals themselves. In this case, the ‘harm’ would be to Jeffrey as an individual in failing to have a sufficient education to aid in his development as an intelligent adult of which all students are entitled to under the British Columbia Human Rights Code. Again, however, the school districts actions were primarily economically-motivated and did not seek to prevent harm, and therefore, the findings of the Tribunal and Supreme Court of Canada in discrimination against special needs students are well-founded as Paternalism also does not allow for a justifiable limit on liberty. |
Revision as of 14:34, 25 March 2014
Liberty and Paternalism
Liberty and Paternalism depart from previous legal theories and is concerned with the proper limits of law. Both theories have a presumption in favour of liberty for the individual as an inherent right, and any interference by the state on that liberty must be justified.
There are several valid justifications for law’s restriction of liberty:
- The Harm Principle
The harm principle allows the restriction of individual liberty by law if it promotes the prevention of serious harm towards others in society.
- Paternalism
Paternalism allows for the restriction of individual liberty by law if it protects others from harm through the exercise of that individual’s liberty in harming themselves.
- Legal Moralism
Legal Moralism allows the restriction of individual liberty by law is where the individual’s actions undermine societal morals and values.
- The Offence Principle
The offence principle allows for the restriction of individual liberty by law if it ensures that the sensibilities of others are not unduly offended.
John Stuart Mill and Liberty
Mill begins with the presumption of liberty for all individuals. He then is concerned with the proper limits of authority in law on that liberty and feels that liberty itself is inherently difficult and must be carefully controlled.
Mill notes the concept of liberty itself sets limits on authorities through:
- Political Liberties or Rights
Certain immunities of which it is regarded as a breach of duty for an authority to infringe. This is seen today in Canada through our enshrined rights in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and provincial rights codes, including the British Columbia Human Rights Code.
- Constitutional Checks
A system that requires consent from a body of some sort that represents the interests of the community in reviewing the power of authorities. This is seen today in Canada through our Parliamentary system and democratic self-government, whose powers are derived and embodied in the Constitution.
Harm Principal
Mill feels the fundamental party to protect in society is that of the individual. Society provides that protection through law. As society provides protection, Mill asserts that we, as individuals, have a necessary obligation in return to contribute to the maintenance of that society, defend it as necessary, and ensure that we do not contribute to the harm of others within it. As such, Mill believes in a strict application of the harm principle. Prevention of harm itself is not only a sufficient justification for the limiting of individual liberty through law, but prevent ion of harm is a necessary condition of legitimate interference with liberty.
Tyranny of the Majority
Mill noted the popularity of self-government and democratic rule, in which the public itself became part of the authority that controlled the limits on liberty. The problem with self-government is the danger of creating a tyranny of the majority. The Tyranny of the Majority is when society itself becomes the tyrant and collectively imposes its power over the individuals who compose it. Society can and will often pass its own mandates, and if it passes mandates that are incorrect or not necessary, through social tyranny the power of those mandates can become oppressive, enforce conformity, and leave fewer avenues for individuals to escape from improper limits on their liberty. The Tyranny of the Majority includes social tyranny through prevailing opinions and feelings. Mill felt that there needed to be a limit on the inference of collective opinion with individual independence and finding that limit is necessary to protect liberty and prevent political despotism.
Exceptions to the Rule of Liberty
Mill notes that the right to liberty does not apply to children under the age limits set by law for adulthood or ‘nonage’ societies that are ‘backwards’ in their social development. Mill notes that these parties must be protected by others with mature faculties against harm from their own actions and the actions of others.
Gerald Dworkin and Paternalism
Paternalism challenges Liberty and expands on the idea of the harm principle as justification to limiting individual liberty. Paternalism argues that interference with individual liberty is not only justified in prevent harm to others, but is also justified in preventing harm to the person themselves. This is also true in cases where prevention of individual harm incidentally leads to prevention of harm to third parties. Paternalistic interference preserves autonomy, which Dworkin asserts is analogous to liberty.
Dworkin introduces several other justifications for limits on liberty:
- Limiting liberty where it produces irreversible and destructive changes of personal liberty/autonomy. In example, through irrational choices or addiction.
- Limiting liberty where decisions are made under extreme psychological pressure and the risks are not freely chosen or understood. In example, suicide or confessions.
Contrasting Liberty and Paternalism with Other Legal Theories
Many of the concepts considered as valid justifications for the limits of law fit within the moral framework of earlier theories set forth by legal positivists and natural law theorists. For example, the harm principle itself is focused on the interests of every person not to be seriously harmed by others. This interest is certainly a requirement of the common good found in both positivism and natural law and supports integration of morality within a legal framework. However, it should be noted that Liberty theorists will stress the fact that liberty itself allows for expression of morality, therefore justification of law comes from restraint on limiting liberty through creation of social rights which embody moral values preventing harm in society, not through justification that the moral values themselves create law.
Application of Liberty and Paternalism to Moore v. British Columbia (Education)
The Court in Moore v. British Columbia (Education) uphold the presumption of individual liberty; specifically, the liberty of students to develop their individual potential and acquire the knowledge and skills needed to contribute to a healthy democratic society through education. This liberty is protected in the acknowledgement by the provincial government that there is an inherent right to access to education under section 8 of the British Columbia Human Rights Code. Further, the Code also set out the limits of which the government must adhere in order to prevent discrimination against individuals on the basis of this right and the liberty is protects. These facts strongly follow Mill’s concept of individual liberty and the idea that the creation of political rights and liberties is one way to ensure limits on authoritative powers from infringing liberty. It is important to note that the Court stresses the importance of how all children should be afforded equal opportunities to develop their full potential through education. In fact, the Court goes as far as to stress the importance of protection of children against the harm of receiving poor education or limited access to the education they need. In Jeffrey’s case, at the Tribunal level, experts clearly agreed that Jeffrey suffered as a result of having poor access to facilities to address his disability and noted sufficient access to those facilities would have benefitted him in the long run. The Court here submits that the public school system has a duty to provide sufficient access to education. These ideas fit Mills presumption that the doctrine of Liberty is only applicable to those of mature faculties and that those who do not have them, children under the legal age or ‘nonage’ societies’, must be protected by those that do against harm from their own actions (in this case, Jeffrey) and actions of others (in this case, the school district and Province). This idea of protection of children against harm easily brings in the liberalism theory of the Harm Principle set out by Mill. The Harm Principle allows the restriction of individual liberty by law if it promotes the prevention of serious harm towards others in society. In Jeffrey’s case, the ‘others’ in society are those children with special educational needs, and the ‘harm’ that occurs is their inability to access education to allow full liberty to develop their skills and knowledge. In this case, the actions of the school district did not meet this justification. Their actions were stressed as being one of economic needs to allow the cutbacks to the programs for special needs students that Jeffrey required. Further, the actions by the school district indiscriminately allowed some programs, such as the Outdoor School, while cutting others, such as the Diagnostic Centre. At no point did the actions of the school district seek to prevent harm to special needs children in the education system, of which, had the school district sought to do so it may have allowed the limits they imposed under the Harm Principle. This is extremely prevalent in the decision by the school district to not even consider alternative options for special needs children in their public schools before cutting the programs completely. Paternalism notes that not only are limits against liberty justified in situations of harm to others as stressed by Mill, but Dworkin allows limits against liberty as justified in situations of harm to the individuals themselves. In this case, the ‘harm’ would be to Jeffrey as an individual in failing to have a sufficient education to aid in his development as an intelligent adult of which all students are entitled to under the British Columbia Human Rights Code. Again, however, the school districts actions were primarily economically-motivated and did not seek to prevent harm, and therefore, the findings of the Tribunal and Supreme Court of Canada in discrimination against special needs students are well-founded as Paternalism also does not allow for a justifiable limit on liberty.