Difference between revisions of "Course:Law3020/2014WT1/Group D/Positivism"

From Kumu Wiki - TRU
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
(15 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
== Legal Positivism ==
 
== Legal Positivism ==
  
Legal positivists view law as a science, with concrete elements which makes a law valid if the components are met. In contrast with natural law, legal positivists are not concerned with the content of the law, but rather it is concerned with the process of how the law was enacted. Since moral is not a necessary element of positive law, there is a possibility for a valid law to be unjust. To illustrate this, legal positivists point to the fact that Nazi laws were valid.
+
Legal positivism is best understood as a reaction to natural law theory. Legal positivists rejects the idea that law is teleological and that there is a morally good end that the law is striving to achieve. Legal positivists believe that morality is not a necessary component of a valid law, and that it is possible for immoral laws to be valid laws. To illustrate this point, we can look to the apartheid systems in Nazi Germany or South Africa as examples of legal systems that had immoral, yet valid, laws. Although both natural law theorists and legal positivists believe that there is a moral obligation to obey 'valid laws', the latter believes that the obligation to obey is based on the the fact that the law itself was validly enacted.  
  
John Austin is a legal positivist who believes that a law is valid if the following criteria is satisfied:
+
===John Austin===
 +
 
 +
[[File:John Austin.jpg|thumbnail|John Austin]]
 +
 
 +
John Austin is one of the founding legal positivists. According to Austin, human behaviour is governed by three distinct directives. First, God's Law is a religious concept which is separate from human law. Some of God's laws are revealed, while the rest must be discovered through the index of utility to determine as best they can what God's commands are. Second, positive morality are rules that fall short of actual laws in that they are missing one or more of essential elements which makes a law valid. They include societal norms such as manners, customs, club rules, international law and English constitutional law. Third, positive law is a command, issued by superiors to subordinates, and backed by the threat of sanctions.
 +
<br />
 +
<br />
 +
 
 +
For Austin, a law is valid if the following criteria is satisfied:
 
<br />
 
<br />
 
(1) Law must be empirically provable;
 
(1) Law must be empirically provable;
Line 10: Line 18:
 
<br />
 
<br />
 
(3) It must be created in accordance with the rule of the law making jurisdiction.
 
(3) It must be created in accordance with the rule of the law making jurisdiction.
 +
<br />
 +
<br />
 +
 +
According to Austin, the role of the sovereign is to give generalized commands that apply to society. The role of the judges is to use these generalized commands and to make specific commands in accordance to the facts of a case. Judges are not part of the sovereign, but nonetheless has the power to make specific commands based on the authority delegated to them by the sovereign. Judge-made law (the common law) has the effect of a valid law so long as it does not conflict with positive law.
  
== Application to Case ==
+
== Case Study: Eldridge v B.C. ==
In the present case, John Austin would agree that the Medical and Health Care Services Act and the Hospital Insurance Act were created in accordance with the rule of law making jurisdiction and so it is a valid law. According to the provision in the Medical and Health Care Services Act, the discretion to determine which services would be covered under the Medical Services Plan was delegated to the Medical Services Commission. John Austin would reason that delegated authority is a valid exercise of the legislators' power and so the Commission is also a valid authority because it was created by a valid law-making process from the elected parties, whom the bulk of society are in a habit of obedience or submission to. In exercising its authority, John Austin would reason that the Commission's choice not to cover sign language interpreters is a "command of the sovereign" and is therefore within its law making jurisdiction. Although the Commission's choice infringes upon the rights of individuals who are deaf from fully benefitting from the health care system, the Commission, as a delegated sovereign, is not bound to ensure that the provision must aim towards a morally worthy end.
+
In the ''[http://scc-csc.lexum.com/scc-csc/scc-csc/en/item/1552/index.do Eldridge]'' case, John Austin would agree that the ''Medical and Health Care Services Act'' and the ''Hospital Insurance Act'' are valid laws because they were enacted by the legislature, whom the bulk of society is in the habit of obedience or submission to. However, Austin would not agree with the court's decision in applying the ''Charter'' to analyze the validity of theses Acts because in the eyes of Austin, the ''Charter'' is not a valid law because its purpose is to bind the sovereign.
 +
<br />
  
Issue arises when validly enacted laws are in conflict with one another. According to the court, when there is conflict between a law and the Charter, we must apply the Oakes Test to determine to determine if the limit is demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. The Oakes framework is as follows:
 
  
First, the objective of the legislation must be pressing and substantial. Second, the means chosen to attain this legislative end must be reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. In order to satisfy the second requirement, three criteria must be satisfied: (1) the violation of the right must be rationally connected to the aim of the legislation; (2) the impugned provision must minimally impair the Charter guarantee; and (3) the deleterious effects on the individual whose rights are limited must be proportional to the objective and to the salutary effects of the measures.
+
'''Medical and Health Care Services Act and the Hospital Insurance Act'''
 +
<br />
 +
John Austin would likely agree that the ''[http://www.bclaws.ca/EPLibraries/bclaws_new/document/ID/freeside/00_96286_01 Medical and Health Care Services Act]'' and the ''[http://www.canlii.org/en/qc/laws/stat/rsq-c-a-28/latest/rsq-c-a-28.html Hospital Insurance Act]'' are valid laws because the meet the Austin's three criteria mentioned above. First, it is clear that the Acts are empirically provable. Second, it is a command issued by superiors to subordinates, and backed by sanctions. In British Columbia, the sovereign is the aggregate body of the British Columbia legislature because the bulk of society are in a habit of obedience to them. Through the exercise of their law-making power, the BC legislature enacted the ''Medical and Health Care Services Act'' in order to regulate the health care system. Within this Act, the BC legislature delegated some powers to the Medical Services Commission to oversee the day-to-day operation of this social system. Among these powers is the Commission's discretion to determine which services would be covered under the ''Medical Services Plan''. Specifically, the Act authorizes the Commission to determine which service is covered under the Medical Plan, and that the only restriction to its discretion is that the power must not be used in a manner that is contrary to section 7 of the ''[http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/acts/c-6/page-2.html#h-6 Canada Health Act]'' (''Eldridge v British Columbia'', [1997] 3 SCR 624 at paragraph 28). John Austin would reason that the Commission is a valid authority because it was created by the sovereign. By exercising their power, the Commission made a decision to not include sign language interpreters as a medical expense, which can be interpreted as a "command of the sovereign". Lastly, the Acts were created in accordance with the proper legislative process.
 +
<br />
 +
 
 +
 
 +
'''The Charter of Rights and Freedoms'''
 +
<br />
 +
According to the court in ''Eldridge'', when a provision is in violation of the ''Charter'', the court has the duty to ensure that the infringement can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. In this case, the court found that the provision was contrary to the principles of fundamental justice because the failure to provide coverage for sign language interpreters was not a minimal impairment of the s.15(1) rights of individuals who are deaf (''Eldridge v British Columbia'', [1997] 3 SCR 624 at paragraph 94).  
  
In the present case, John Austin would agree that the provision and s.15(1) of the Charter are both valid laws. To determine which law is superior over the other, John Austin would most likely agree that since the Canadian system is based on constitutional supremacy, the Constitution is the supreme law in Canada. According to the rule of law making jurisdiction, all laws must be in compliance with the Constitution. John Austin would probably support the use of the Oakes Test developed by the courts as the analytic framework for determining whether a law is a reasonable limit under the Charter. This approach is permissible by John Austin because judicial decisions are specific commands. Judges are considered as holding lawful authority because he views a judge as acting as a minister who carries out the limited authority which has been delegated to him or her by the state. In addition, this framework conforms with the positivists' aim to use a scientific method for determining the validity of a law.
+
John Austin would disagree with the court's analysis because he would not recognize the ''Charter'' as a valid law. The issue with the ''Charter'' is that it fails Austin's basic element that a valid law must be a command issued by a superior to its subordinates. In this case, the ''Charter'' attempts to bind the authority of the sovereign, which is contrary to Austin's view that the sovereign cannot be bound by law. Although the Medical Services Commission's choice to not cover sign language interpreters infringes upon the rights of individuals who are deaf from fully benefiting from the health care system, Austin is not concerned with promoting equality of health care among citizens. Austin would likely state that the difference in access to health care, although unjust, is still valid law. As previously mentioned, legal positivists accept the fact that valid laws can co-exist with unjust valid. Under these circumstances, Austin would classify the ''Charter'' under positive morality since it purports to bind the sovereign.
 +
<div style="text-align: right;">[[Course:Law3020/2014WT1/Group_D/Separation_Thesis|Next: Separation Thesis]]</div>
 +
<div style="text-align: left;">[[Course:Law3020/2014WT1/Group_D/Natural_Law|Previous: Natural Law]]</div>

Latest revision as of 20:47, 27 March 2014

Legal Positivism

Legal positivism is best understood as a reaction to natural law theory. Legal positivists rejects the idea that law is teleological and that there is a morally good end that the law is striving to achieve. Legal positivists believe that morality is not a necessary component of a valid law, and that it is possible for immoral laws to be valid laws. To illustrate this point, we can look to the apartheid systems in Nazi Germany or South Africa as examples of legal systems that had immoral, yet valid, laws. Although both natural law theorists and legal positivists believe that there is a moral obligation to obey 'valid laws', the latter believes that the obligation to obey is based on the the fact that the law itself was validly enacted.

John Austin

John Austin

John Austin is one of the founding legal positivists. According to Austin, human behaviour is governed by three distinct directives. First, God's Law is a religious concept which is separate from human law. Some of God's laws are revealed, while the rest must be discovered through the index of utility to determine as best they can what God's commands are. Second, positive morality are rules that fall short of actual laws in that they are missing one or more of essential elements which makes a law valid. They include societal norms such as manners, customs, club rules, international law and English constitutional law. Third, positive law is a command, issued by superiors to subordinates, and backed by the threat of sanctions.

For Austin, a law is valid if the following criteria is satisfied:
(1) Law must be empirically provable;
(2) It must be a command, issued by superiors to subordinates, and backed by the threat of sanctions; and
(3) It must be created in accordance with the rule of the law making jurisdiction.

According to Austin, the role of the sovereign is to give generalized commands that apply to society. The role of the judges is to use these generalized commands and to make specific commands in accordance to the facts of a case. Judges are not part of the sovereign, but nonetheless has the power to make specific commands based on the authority delegated to them by the sovereign. Judge-made law (the common law) has the effect of a valid law so long as it does not conflict with positive law.

Case Study: Eldridge v B.C.

In the Eldridge case, John Austin would agree that the Medical and Health Care Services Act and the Hospital Insurance Act are valid laws because they were enacted by the legislature, whom the bulk of society is in the habit of obedience or submission to. However, Austin would not agree with the court's decision in applying the Charter to analyze the validity of theses Acts because in the eyes of Austin, the Charter is not a valid law because its purpose is to bind the sovereign.


Medical and Health Care Services Act and the Hospital Insurance Act
John Austin would likely agree that the Medical and Health Care Services Act and the Hospital Insurance Act are valid laws because the meet the Austin's three criteria mentioned above. First, it is clear that the Acts are empirically provable. Second, it is a command issued by superiors to subordinates, and backed by sanctions. In British Columbia, the sovereign is the aggregate body of the British Columbia legislature because the bulk of society are in a habit of obedience to them. Through the exercise of their law-making power, the BC legislature enacted the Medical and Health Care Services Act in order to regulate the health care system. Within this Act, the BC legislature delegated some powers to the Medical Services Commission to oversee the day-to-day operation of this social system. Among these powers is the Commission's discretion to determine which services would be covered under the Medical Services Plan. Specifically, the Act authorizes the Commission to determine which service is covered under the Medical Plan, and that the only restriction to its discretion is that the power must not be used in a manner that is contrary to section 7 of the Canada Health Act (Eldridge v British Columbia, [1997] 3 SCR 624 at paragraph 28). John Austin would reason that the Commission is a valid authority because it was created by the sovereign. By exercising their power, the Commission made a decision to not include sign language interpreters as a medical expense, which can be interpreted as a "command of the sovereign". Lastly, the Acts were created in accordance with the proper legislative process.


The Charter of Rights and Freedoms
According to the court in Eldridge, when a provision is in violation of the Charter, the court has the duty to ensure that the infringement can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. In this case, the court found that the provision was contrary to the principles of fundamental justice because the failure to provide coverage for sign language interpreters was not a minimal impairment of the s.15(1) rights of individuals who are deaf (Eldridge v British Columbia, [1997] 3 SCR 624 at paragraph 94).

John Austin would disagree with the court's analysis because he would not recognize the Charter as a valid law. The issue with the Charter is that it fails Austin's basic element that a valid law must be a command issued by a superior to its subordinates. In this case, the Charter attempts to bind the authority of the sovereign, which is contrary to Austin's view that the sovereign cannot be bound by law. Although the Medical Services Commission's choice to not cover sign language interpreters infringes upon the rights of individuals who are deaf from fully benefiting from the health care system, Austin is not concerned with promoting equality of health care among citizens. Austin would likely state that the difference in access to health care, although unjust, is still valid law. As previously mentioned, legal positivists accept the fact that valid laws can co-exist with unjust valid. Under these circumstances, Austin would classify the Charter under positive morality since it purports to bind the sovereign.

Next: Separation Thesis
Previous: Natural Law